Skip to main content
  • Research Article
  • Open access
  • Published:

A Mathematical Revisit of Modeling the Majority Voting on Fixed-Income Quadratic Taxations

Abstract

Analyzing voting on income taxation usually implies mathematically cumbersome models. Moreover, a majority voting winner does not usually exist in such setups. Therefore, it is important to mathematically describe those cases in which a majority winner exists, at least for the basic models of voting on income taxation. We provide a complete mathematical description of those income distribution functions for which a majority winning tax exists (or does not exist), in the quadratic taxation model à la Roemer (1999), with tax schedules that are not necessarily purely redistributive. As an intermediate step, we identify by the corner method what are the most preferred taxes of the individuals, when taxation is not purely redistributive. Finally, we prove that for both purely and nonpurely redistributive quadratic taxations, the sufficient inequality condition of De Donder and Hindriks (2004) on the income distribution functions, for the existence of a Condorcet winner, can be relaxed to a broader condition.

1. Introduction

One important question that the positive theory of income taxation tries to answer is why marginal-rate progressive tax schedules are preponderant in democracies. An heuristic argument commonly invoked to explain this stylized fact resides in the observation that in general, the number of relatively poor (self-interest) voters exceeds that of richer ones. Nevertheless, mathematically formalizing the argument is not an easy task and the literature is rather inconclusive in this respect.

One very important difficulty which arises when studying these issues is that usually the existence of a majority winner (i.e., Condorcet winner) is not guaranteed. Voting games over redistributive tax schedules lack in general the existence of a static equilibrium (see Marhuenda and Ortuño-Ortin [1], Hindriks [2], De Donder and Hindriks [3]). The seminal papers of Romer [4, 5] and Roberts [6] consider only flat rate taxes in order to make use of the median voter theorem, after imposing some natural additional restrictions. However, the overrestrictive assumption of linear tax schemes does not provide the framework to investigate important issues like the high prevalence of marginal-rate progressive taxations in democracies. Therefore, many authors study the basic problem of voting on income taxations in terms of larger classes of tax functions.

Gouveia and Oliver [7] work with two-bracket piecewise linear functions, Cukierman and Meltzer [8] and Roemer [9] study quadratic tax functions, while Carbonell and Klor [10] consider a representative democracy model that allows for the class of all piecewise linear tax schedules. Marhuenda and Ortuño-Ortin [11] allow for the class of all concave or convex tax functions, proving by Jensen's inequality that for income distributions with the median below the mean income, any concave tax scheme receives less popular support than any convex tax scheme.

Carbonell and Ok [12] provide a two-party voting game in which each party (whose objective is to win the elections) proposes tax schemes from an unrestricted set of admissible functions and the voters selfishly vote for the tax that taxes them less. Establishing the existence of mixed equilibria, they identify certain cases in which marginal-rate progressive taxes are chosen almost surely by the political parties. However, Carbonell and Ok [12] find that if the tax policy space is not artificially constrained, the support of at least one equilibrium cannot be obtained within the set of marginal-rate progressive taxes. This result is in the same line with the one of Klor [13], who shows that a majority of poor voters does not necessarily imply progressive taxation for a more general policy space than the one in Marhuenda and Ortuño-Ortin [11].

Although it is hard to find an economically meaningful way of restricting the admissible set of income tax functions, the literature on voting over income taxes which are chosen from restricted policy spaces provides useful and powerful insights into the general problem. In particular, the quadratic model was very much used in the literature to generate interesting results. Cukierman and Meltzer [8] analyze the conditions under which the median voter's most preferred tax policy is a majority winner, in quadratic distortionary tax environments. Roemer [9] uses the quadratic taxation framework to define a different solution concept than the majority winner, based on the need to reach an intraparty agreement between the "opportunists" and the "militants" of the parties. In the same setup of fixed income (i.e., income not distorted by taxes) and quadratic taxations as the one in Roemer [9], Hindriks [2] establishes the inevitable vote cycling theorem.

De Donder and Hindriks [14] introduce preferences for leisure in the quadratic taxation model and study the voting process over tax schedules using other political equilibria than the Condorcet winner. For the quadratic model with fixed income, De Donder and Hindriks [3] show that incentive constraints result in the policy set to be closed and that individuals all have corner solutions over this set. They also provide a necessary and sufficient condition on the income distribution such that a Condorcet winner exists. Moreover, for income distributions with the median less than the mean, if a majority winner exists then it involves maximum progressivity.

This paper provides a complete description of those income distribution functions for which a majority winning tax exists (or does not exist), when the quadratic taxation model is not purely redistributive. For reasons of completeness, the analysis is not limited only to right skewed income distributions (which are empirically predominant), but there has been also considered the case of the left skewed income distributions. We also identify what are the most preferred taxes of the individuals (and the corresponding income groups they can be classified in, based on the preferred policies), when taxation has more than a purely redistributive purpose. Moreover, we show in this paper that the sufficient condition of De Donder and Hindriks [3], imposed on the income distribution functions in order to insure the existence of a Condorcet winner, can be relaxed to a broader condition.

The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 presents the model. Section 3 states and proves the results. Section 4 discusses and draws the conclusions.

2. The Model

The economy consists of a large number of individuals who differ in their (fixed) income. Each individual is characterized by his/her income . The income distribution can be described by a continuous function , differentiable almost everywhere and strictly increasing on the interval . Each individual with income has strictly increasing preferences on the set of its possible net incomes. For any Lebesque measurable set , the associated Lebesque-Stieltjes probability measure induced by is denoted by and it is defined as .

For better comprehensibility of the text, any parameter calculated based on the distribution is denoted using the letter (e.g., the mean is , the median is denoted by , the noncentered moment of second order is , and the variance of the income distribution is ), while refers to a random income in the interval .

The fixed amount should be collected through means of a tax imposed on the agents. When , the tax is purely redistributive. It is assumed that there is no tax evasion, and there are no distortions induced by the taxation system in the economy (i.e., the income is fixed), respectively. The set of admissible tax functions satisfies certain conditions. For a given and , denotes the set of all functions such that (without the second and third conditions below, we would have a resource redistribution problem like in Grandmont [15], which is known not to have a Condorcet winner; see at the end of this section the definition for a majority winner.)

(1), for all ;

(2), for all ;

(3), for all ;

(4)

A tax schedule is (marginally) progressive (regressive) if and only if is convex (concave). In the following, we consider only quadratic taxes of the form , . (The analysis also includes the case of linear tax schedules, when the coefficient "" takes the zero value.) We restrict our analysis to , the set of quadratic tax functions that satisfy the feasibility conditions (1)–(4). It can be easily proved that conditions (1) to (4) restrict the set of quadratic feasible taxes to functions of the form , , which satisfy the following conditions:

(21)

Note that for every given distribution and feasible , to every tax from , it corresponds one and only one element in the feasible area (FA), and vice versa. Thus, the set of feasible quadratic tax policies can be illustrated as follows (the intervals for are mathematically well defined due to the inequality , more specifically from .)

(i)The case is represented in Figure 1(a).

(ii)The case is represented in Figure 1(b).

  1. (iii)

    The case is represented in Figure 1(c).

Figure 1
figure 1

Feasibility areas for different cases of the collected tax amount .

The coordinates of the vertices of the above polygons are easily obtained by elementary computations and are given by

progressive taxations: , , ,

regressive taxations: , , ,

no taxation: , confiscation policy: .

Figure 1 presents the feasibility areas for different cases of the collected amount . These areas are determined by the (FA) conditions as follows: the first two conditions determine the interior and the sides of the parallelogram. The third condition is the tax revenue requirement constraint, graphically identified by the half-plane situated above the line .

For the case depicted in Figure 1(a), the tax is the most progressive, is the most regressive, and and are out of the feasible area (FA). If then is not feasible, while if then . For the case depicted in Figure 1(b), the tax policy is the most progressive, is the most regressive, and the tax policies , , , are not feasible. For the case depicted in Figure 1(c), the tax schedule is the most progressive, is the most regressive, and the tax policies , , , are not feasible.

A majority (or Condorcet) winning tax policy is a pair in the feasible set such that is preferred by a majority of individuals to any other feasible pair in . An equivalent definition used in our proofs is the following: a tax function is a majority winner if and only if there is no objection to it (given , a tax policy is an objection to if ). We denote by the set of all objections to the taxation function . Therefore, the above definitions for being a Condorcet winner are equivalent to the condition .

If , by considering and , De Donder and Hindriks [3] defined the low middle and large income groups which are obtained based on the three intervals and divide . Note as well that . Nevertheless, the other two fixed values of the income are important for the analysis that follows. Those values are . In the same spirit as the interpretation offered by De Donder and Hindriks [3], the voters are poor with relatively high income, and are rich voters with relatively low income, respectively. As one can see in the section of results, these values will play an important role for stating the necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of a Condorcet winner in the described environment.

3. Results

In order to identify the majority winning tax policies (if any), the first step is to characterize the tax policies that are objections to a given tax policy . Therefore, we need first to determine the sign of the function on the interval and then to find the Lebesgue measure of the set on which the difference function is negative. The following lemma presents the way in which the two roots of the quadratic function vary. Since the difference function is , , then it is sufficient to study the sign of the following quadratic function: , , . (We will analyze in the lemma only the case when ; the case will be discussed separately each time when it occurs in our discussion.)

Lemma 3.1.

Let , , , and , and let . Then, for each , the quadratic function has two real roots and , which vary as functions of as it is shown in Table 1, where and .

Table 1 The behavior of and .

Proof of Lemma 3.1.

The discriminant of can be written as ; hence has two real roots. For each , we will denote by and by the smallest and, respectively the largest of the roots. After short computations, we get and .

The behavior of the roots as functions of can be elementary studied by computing their derivatives and the limits at the endpoints of . Since , for each and , for each , then and are increasing functions of . The limits of the functions and at the endpoints of the definition domain are , , , .

Elementary computations give us the following results: , , , , , and . Due to the previous computations, the behavior of the functions and is as presented in Table 1.

The purely redistributive tax policies that individuals prefer are described in De Donder and Hindriks [3]; all individuals in the same income class prefer the same policy. The low income group prefers confiscation policy (represented by the point in the feasible region (FA) when ), the middle income class prefers the maximum progressivity (represented by the point if ), and no taxation (the point ) is preferred by the high income group. The next lemma shows how this simple description changes when the tax schedules are not purely redistributive. A sketch of the proof is provided after stating the result and further details are available upon request.

Lemma 3.2.

The preferred tax for an individual with the income is

(1)the case (Figure 1(a)):

(1a)   for (for the income , the individual is indifferent between the taxes on the segment ),

(1b)   for (for the income , the individual is indifferent between the taxes on the segment ),

(1c)   for (for the income , the individual is indifferent between the taxes on the segment ),

(1d)   for ,

(2)the case (Figure 1(b)):

(2a)   for (for the income , the individual is indifferent between the taxes on the segment ),

(2b)   for (for the income , the individual is indifferent between the taxes on the segment ),

(2c)  similar to (1d),

(3)the case (Figure 1(c)):

(3a)  similar to (2a),

(3b)   for (for the income , the individual is indifferent between the taxes on the segment ),

(3c)   for .

Proof of Lemma 3.2.

An individual with income prefers the tax for which the difference is maximum. Hence, we have to solve the following linear programming problem: determine the maximum of the function , subject to the constraints , , , . The problem can be elementary solved by using the corner method.

Irrespective of the amount that should be collected, the low income group prefers the tax policy that equalizes the posttax income. The middle income group prefers the most progressive tax policy. The high income group is divided in a lower part and an upper one by the value . The upper part always prefers a regressive taxation when (in fact, for high values of the amount to be collected, this income group prefers the most regressive tax schedule—see Lemma 3.2(3c)) above). The lower part of the high income group usually behaves as the middle income group, except for the case of low levels of . Even in such a case (see Lemma 3.2(1c)), the lower part of the high income group prefers a progressive taxation instead of a regressive one. These observations motivate a possible redefinition of the middle income group from to . However, in order to have clear comparisons between the results in De Donder and Hindriks [3] and our results, we consider as the lower part of the high income group, while the interval keeps its interpretation of middle income class.

Having Lemmas 3.1 and 3.2 at hand, we are in the position to provide a complete description of the cases in which there is a majority winning tax, or when there is not. The next proposition can be immediately obtained from the lemmas and it is a first step to provide such a description.

Proposition 3.3.

The following assertions hold.

(1)If , then for each the tax policy is a majority winner (a Condorcet winner).

(2)If , then for each the tax policy is a majority winner (a Condorcet winner).

(3)If and , then the tax policy is a majority winner (a Condorcet winner).

Proof of Proposition 3.3.

  1. (1)

    Let be defined by . In order to prove that under the conditions imposed by the hypothesis the function is a majority winner, it is sufficient to show there is no objection to it. Suppose by contrary that there exists . Then , satisfies the feasibility conditions (FA).

Figure 2 presents the feasibility areas for the coefficients and of the functions , which occur in the proofs of the Propositions 3.3 and 3.4. The feasibility areas are determined in a similar way as for the -feasible taxes: a parallelogram is separated by the line generated by the budget constraint condition.

We denote by , , where by and we mean and , respectively. From the feasibility conditions (FA) for the tax function , we obtain that the coefficients and must satisfy , , and . The feasible area for the coefficients and can be represented as it is shown in the Figure 2(a).

If , then and since .

If and , then and the roots of satisfy the inequalities and (see Lemma 3.1). In this case (see Table 2, line 2).

If and , then and the roots of satisfy the inequalities and (see Lemma 3.1). In this case (see Table 2, line 3).

So, for any pair which satisfy the feasibility conditions, the function cannot be an objection to the tax function and the tax function is a majority winner.

  1. (2)

    We will prove that there is no objection to the tax policy given by . Suppose, by contrary that there exists . Let be the tax policy given by and let , , where by and we mean and , respectively. The feasibility conditions for conduct to the following conditions on the coefficients and : . The feasible area for the coefficients and can be represented as it is shown in the Figure 2(b).

If , then and .

If , then and the roots of satisfy the inequalities and . In this case (see Table 2, line 4).

If then and the roots of satisfy the inequalities and . In this case (see Table 2, line 5).

So, for any pair which belongs to the feasible area, the function cannot be an objection to the tax function and the tax policy is a Condorcet winner.

  1. (3)

    We will prove that in this case there is no objection to the tax policy given by . Suppose by contrary that there exists . Let be the tax policy given by . The feasibility area for the coefficients and is presented in Figure 2(c).

If , then and .

If , then , , and (see Table 2, line 6).

If , then , , and (see Table 2, line 5).

In conclusion for any and such that the pair belongs to the feasible area, the function is not an objection to the tax function . This completes the proof.

Table 2 The sign of the function .
Figure 2
figure 2

Feasibility areas for the coefficients and .

Note that if , the result from Proposition 3.3(1) was first obtained by De Donder and Hindriks [3] (see Proposition 1(a) in that paper). Proposition 3.3(1) is a generalization: it states that for every feasible value of , if a majority of individuals is in the low income group, then the voting outcome will determine that all individuals are equal in the posttax income. The second and third parts of the proposition have no empirical relevance since there is overwhelming evidence ruling out negatively skewed income distributions. However, these parts are reported for the purpose of completeness, such that Proposition 3.3 and the next three form together a knit result. (In fact, the results from the last two parts of Proposition 3.3 are very logical; e.g., the second part states that an existing majority of individuals in the upper part of the high income class will induce as a voting outcome the regressive tax system preferred by all the individuals with income in that subclass.)

The next two propositions are central for the current paper. We start with the second proposition, that provides a necessary condition for a majority winning tax to exist.

Proposition 3.4.

Let be such that .

(1)If , then for each the tax policy is a majority winner (a Condorcet winner).

(2)If , then for each the tax policy is a majority winner (a Condorcet winner).

(3)If , then for each the tax policy is a majority winner (a Condorcet winner).

Proof of Proposition 3.4.

  1. (1)

    We have to prove that there is no objection to the tax policy given by . Let be a tax policy given by and let , , , where and . The feasibility conditions for determine the following inequalities: , , and  . The feasible area for the coefficients and can be represented as it is shown in the Figure 2(d).

If , then and , which is not an objection to the tax function .

If , then . If , then , and (see Table 2, line 7). If , then , and (see Table 2, line 8). If , then , and (see Table 2, line 9).

In conclusion, for any pair which belongs to the feasible area, the function cannot be an objection to the tax function . Hence, the tax policy given by is a Condorcet winner.

  1. (2)

    We have to prove that there is no objection to the tax policy given by . Let be a tax policy given by , and let , , , where and . The feasibility conditions for determine the following inequalities: , , and . The feasible area for the coefficients and can be represented as it is shown in Figure 2(e).

If , then and .

If , then and the proof is similar to the correspondent case of the 1st part.

If , then , and after splitting in subcases , , and the proofs are similar to the correspondent cases of the 1st part.

Hence, the tax policy is a majority winner.

  1. (3)

    We have to prove that there is no objection to the tax policy given by . If is given by and and , then the feasibility area for is given by the conditions: , , and . The feasible area for the coefficients and can be represented as it is shown in the Figure 2(f).

In this case and . After splitting in subcases and , then the proofs are similar to the correspondent parts of the 1st case.

Hence, the tax policy is a majority winner. This completes the proof.

If , the result from Proposition 3.4(1) was first established by De Donder and Hindriks [3] (see Proposition 1(b) in that paper). However, their result was obtained by imposing the more restrictive condition . In other words, for every distribution function such that , we have with certainty that the maximum progressivity tax is the voting outcome, as far as the median voter prefers this policy. This result does not depend on whether the tax is purely redistributive or not. For purely redistributive taxes, a specific proof is provided in Curt, Litan and Filip [16].

Therefore, it is enough to have a majority formed by individuals between the upper part of the low income group and the lower part of the high income group, in order to obtain support for the highest tax progressivity. Our next example proves that the necessary condition in Proposition 1(b) in De Donder and Hindriks [3] is overrestrictive. We construct a function with , in which case the conclusions of our Proposition 3.4 trivially apply.

Example 3.5.

Let be the distribution function given by

(31)

The mean income , greater than the median income which is equal to . Routine calculations show that , , , , , and .

For this income distribution, our Proposition 3.4 directly applies (while there is no need to check the necessary and sufficient condition of Proposition 3 in De Donder and Hindriks [3]).

The first and third parts of the Proposition 3.4 advocate the idea that the majority winning tax is the most progressive one, when the median voter is part of the middle income group. Regarding the intuition of the result, straightforward and not surprising is the case in which there is a majority within the middle income group (i.e., ); hence, the middle class can afford to minimize its tax, and the burden remains on the rich and the poor.

Not intuitively straightforward is the case in which the middle income group cannot form a majority coalition, but there exists a majority formed by individuals between the upper part of the low income group and the lower part of the high income group (i.e., ). The policy preferred by the middle income group remains the only majority winner because there is disagreement within the low income group, between the upper part and the rest of the group, and within the high income group, between the lower part and the rest, respectively. Although the second part of the proposition implies a left skewed distribution of the income (not existent in practice), the result is in the same line with the first and third parts: as far as the median voter prefers the tax (together with all the individuals in the subclass to which the median voter belongs), then the majority winner must consist of that policy.

The next proposition characterizes the class of income distributions for which the model does not provide a Condorcet winner.

Proposition 3.6.

Let be such that .

(1)Let . If there is such that , then for each there is no majority winner (Condorcet winner).

  1. (2)

    If , and satisfies the previous conditions (in Proposition 3.6(1)), then there is no majority winner (Condorcet winner).

Proof of Proposition 3.6.

In order to prove the result, it is sufficient for each tax policy to find another tax policy that is an objection to the tax , that is, . Let be a given tax policy. In our attempt to determine an objection to the tax policy , we are looking for a pair such that , and . If we denote by , then and . Since the tax policy defined by must satisfy the feasibility conditions (FA), we have to choose such that , , . Due to the fact that , we have the following inequalities: and . So, only if and , there exists such that the previous conditions are satisfied. Since , by applying Lemma 3.1, we obtain: and in conclusion is an objection for .

It remains to analyze the cases and . Let be a tax policy defined by . In order to determine an objection , we look for values , which satisfy the feasibility conditions (FA) and . Since , then and in consequence . If we denote , then and . After short computations, we observe that we must determine such that and . In the case when , then we can choose which satisfies the previous restrictions. The policy tax is an objection to due to the fact that . In the case when , then the objection tax policy can be determined in a similar manner by choosing , such that . In the case when , the objection function can be also obtained by choosing and which satisfy the feasibility conditions and the equality . If we denote , then and . After short computations, we observe that we must determine such that and . In the case when , then we can choose which satisfies the previous restrictions and we get . Hence, is an objection to the tax policy . If , then and in consequence . For , we have to study the case . In this case the tax policy given by is an objection to . This completes the proof.

The next proposition specifies what are the conditions for a majority winner to exist and such that the conclusions of Proposition 3.4 remain valid, even if there cannot be formed a majority by individuals between the upper part of the low income group and the lower part of the high income group.

Proposition 3.7.

Let and . If for each we have , then the conclusions of the Proposition 3.4 are true.

Proof of Proposition 3.7.

Similar to the proof of the Proposition 3.4.

The intuition of this proposition is not straightforward and resides in the same type of arguments invoked by De Donder and Hindriks [3]. The maximum progressivity has majority support due to the disagreement, not only between the lower and upper parts of the high income group, but also among the individuals of the upper part of this income class. Analogous analysis can be performed for the low income class.

To be more specific, for any tax change (represented by the parameter ) involving less progressivity (parameter ) and higher flat tax parameter (), there is always some poor with income higher than who do not find the increase in large enough to compensate for the lower . As well, there is always some rich with income lower than who do not find the decrease in large enough to compensate for the increase in . The group in disagreement with the extremes for a given tax change is larger now than in Proposition 3.4, that is, . Therefore the condition on the distribution of income in Proposition 3.7 ensures that the size of the group is large enough to form a majority, for any possible .

4. Conclusions

We identified what are the most preferred taxes of the individuals (and the corresponding income groups they can be classified in, based on the preferred policies), for every case of taxation that has more than a purely redistributive purpose (meaning that the tax should collect some positive amount ). In particular, we have proved that if the model departs from the purely redistributive feature, then, at least within the high income class, the preferences differ between the groups and . This fact is essential to understand the result which states that the sufficient condition of De Donder and Hindriks [3] can be relaxed to a broader one.

Indeed, for not very large collected amounts , it is enough to have a majority formed by individuals between the upper part of the low income group and the lower part of the high income group, in order to insure support for the highest tax progressivity (as far as the median voter prefers this policy, that is, ). For , the results in De Donder and Hindriks [3] were obtained around the more restrictive condition . However, the case of purely redistributive taxations can be seen as a limiting case of those situations in which the taxes should collect some positive amounts. Therefore, for and for every distribution function such that , it is also certain that the maximum progressivity is the voting outcome. Example 3.5 shows that the set of the distribution functions with the above property is not empty.

For reasons of completeness, the paper provides an overall description of those income distribution functions for which a majority winning tax exists (or does not exist), when the quadratic taxation model is not purely redistributive. For the same reasons of completeness, the analysis considers both the right skewed income distributions, which are predominant in practice, but also the left skewed ones are analyzed (see the second and third parts of Proposition 3.3, and the second part of Proposition 3.4). We conclude with the idea that, should any political equilibrium different than the Condorcet winner be proposed, it is important to be first tested on those quadratic taxation models without majority winners (both for purely, as well as for nonpurely redistributive taxations). Our work offers a complete mathematical description of this testing set of models.

References

  1. Marhuenda F, Ortuño-Ortín I: Income taxation, uncertainty and stability. Journal of Public Economics 1998, 67(2):285–300. 10.1016/S0047-2727(97)00054-6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Hindriks J: Is there a demand for income tax progressivity? Economics Letters 2001, 73(1):43–50. 10.1016/S0165-1765(01)00459-1

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. De Donder P, Hindriks J: Majority support for progressive income taxation with corner preferences. Public Choice 2004, 118(3–4):437–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Romer T: Individual welfare, majority voting, and the properties of a linear income tax. Journal of Public Economics 1975, 4(2):163–185. 10.1016/0047-2727(75)90016-X

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Romer T: Majority voting on tax parameters. Journal of Public Economics 1977, 7(1):127–133. 10.1016/0047-2727(77)90040-8

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  6. Roberts KWS: Voting over income tax schedules. Journal of Public Economics 1977, 8(3):329–340. 10.1016/0047-2727(77)90005-6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Gouveia M, Oliver D: Voting over flat taxes in an endowment economy. Economics Letters 1996, 50(2):251–258. 10.1016/0165-1765(95)00749-0

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Cukierman A, Meltzer H: A political theory of income taxation. In Political Economy. Edited by: Meltzer A, Cukierman A, Richards F. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK; 1991:78–106.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Roemer JE: The democratic political economy of progressive income taxation. Econometrica 1999, 67(1):1–19. 10.1111/1468-0262.00001

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Carbonell-Nicolau O, Klor EF: Representative democracy and marginal rate progressive income taxation. Journal of Public Economics 2003, 87(5–6):1137–1164. 10.1016/S0047-2727(01)00138-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Marhuenda F, Ortuño-Ortín I: Popular support for progressive taxation. Economics Letters 1995, 48(3–4):319–324. 10.1016/0165-1765(95)94399-G

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Carbonell-Nicolau O, Ok EA: Voting over income taxation. Journal of Economic Theory 2007, 134(1):249–286. 10.1016/j.jet.2006.02.008

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Klor F: On the popular support for progressive taxation. Journal of Public Economic Theory 2003, 5: 593–604. 10.1111/1467-9779.t01-1-00150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. De Donder P, Hindriks J: The politics of progressive income taxation with incentive effects. Journal of Public Economics 2003, 87(11):2491–2505. 10.1016/S0047-2727(02)00051-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Grandmont M: Fiscally stable distributions under majority voting. Advances in Mathematical Economics 2006, 8: 215–230. 10.1007/4-431-30899-7_8

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Curt P, Litan CM, Filip A: Comment on the majority support for progressive income taxation with corner preferences. preprint, 2010

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank Francisco Marhuenda for helpful comments. Cristian Litan aknowledges preliminary discussions with Luis Corchón. Diana Andrada Filip and Paula Curt acknowledge financial support by CNSIS-UEFISCU, project number PNII-IDEI 2366/2008. Cristian Litan acknowledges financial support by CNCSIS-UEFISCSU, project number PN II-RU 415/2010. The usual disclaimer applies.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to DianaAndrada Filip.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 2.0 International License ( https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/2.0 ), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Curt, P., Litan, C. & Filip, D. A Mathematical Revisit of Modeling the Majority Voting on Fixed-Income Quadratic Taxations. J Inequal Appl 2010, 329378 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1155/2010/329378

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1155/2010/329378

Keywords